This file is indexed.

/usr/share/doc/anarchism/html/secD10.html is in anarchism 15.1-5.

This file is owned by root:root, with mode 0o644.

The actual contents of the file can be viewed below.

 1
 2
 3
 4
 5
 6
 7
 8
 9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
<!DOCTYPE html>
<html>
  <head>
  <meta http-equiv="Content-Type" content="text/html; charset=utf-8" />
  <title>D.10 How does capitalism affect technology? | Anarchist Writers</title>
  </head>
  <body>
  <div class="content clear-block">
    <h1>D.10 How does capitalism affect technology?</h1>
<p>Technology has an obvious effect on individual freedom, in some ways increasing it, in others restricting it. However, since capitalism is  a social system based on inequalities of power, it is a truism that technology will reflect those inequalities as it does not develop  in a social vacuum. As Bookchin puts it:</p>
<blockquote><p> <i>"Along side its positive aspects, technological advance has a distinctly negative, socially regressive side. If it is true that technological progress enlarges the historical potentiality for freedom, it is also true that the bourgeois control of technology reinforces the  established organisation of society and everyday life. Technology and the resources of abundance furnish capitalism with the means  for assimilating large sections of society to the established system of hierarchy and authority . . . By their centralistic and  bureaucratic tendencies, the resource of abundance reinforce the  monopolistic, centralistic and bureaucratic tendencies in the  political apparatus . . . [Technology can be used] for perpetuating hierarchy, exploitation and unfreedom."</i> [<b>Post-Scarcity Anarchism</b>, p. 3]
</p></blockquote>
<p>No technology evolves and spreads unless there are people who benefit  from it and have sufficient means to disseminate it. In a capitalist  society, technologies useful to the rich and powerful are generally  the ones that spread. This can be seen from capitalist industry, where  technology has been implemented specifically to deskill the worker, so  replacing the skilled, valued craftsperson with the easily trained and  replaced "mass worker." By making trying to make any individual  worker dispensable, the capitalist hopes to deprive workers of a means  of controlling the relation between their effort on the job and the pay  they receive. In Proudhon's words, the <i>"machine, or the workshop, after having degraded the labourer by giving him a master, completes his degeneracy by reducing him from the rank of artisan to that of common workman."</i> [<b>System of Economical Contradictions</b>, p. 202]</p>
<p>So, unsurprisingly, technology within a hierarchical society will tend to re-enforce hierarchy and domination. Managers/capitalists will select technology that will protect and extend their power (and profits), not weaken it. Thus, while it is often claimed that technology is "neutral" this is not (and can never be) the case. Simply put, "progress" within a hierarchical system will reflect the power structures of that system.</p>
<p>As sociologist George Reitzer notes, technological innovation under a  hierarchical system soon results in <i>"increased control and the replacement  of human with non-human technology. In fact, the replacement of human with non-human technology is very often motivated by a desire for greater control, which of course is motivated by the need for profit-maximisation.  The great sources of uncertainty and unpredictability in any rationalising  system are people . . . McDonaldisation involves the search for the means  to exert increasing control over both employees and customers."</i> [<b>The  McDonaldisation of Society</b>, p. 100] For Reitzer, capitalism is marked  by the <i>"irrationality of rationality,"</i> in which this process of control  results in a system based on crushing the individuality and humanity of  those who live within it.</p>
<p>In this process of controlling employees for the purpose of maximising profit, deskilling comes about because skilled labour is more expensive than unskilled or semi-skilled and skilled workers have more power over  their working conditions and work due to the difficulty in replacing them. Unskilled labour makes it easier to "rationalise" the production  process with methods like Taylorism, a system of strict production schedules  and activities based on the amount of time (as determined by management)  that workers "need" to perform various operations in the workplace, thus  requiring simple, easily analysed and timed movements. As companies  are in competition, each has to copy the most "efficient" (i.e. profit  maximising) production techniques introduced by the others in order to  remain profitable, no matter how dehumanising this may be for workers.  Thus the evil effects of the division of labour and deskilling becoming  widespread. Instead of managing their own work, workers are turned into  human machines in a labour process they do not control, instead being controlled by those who own the machines they use (see also Harry Braverman, <b>Labour and Monopoly Capital: The Degradation of Work in the Twentieth Century</b>).</p>
<p>As Max Stirner noted (echoing Adam Smith), this process of deskilling and controlling work means that <i>"[w]hen everyone is to cultivate himself into man, condemning a man to <b>machine-like labour</b> amounts to the same thing as slavery. . . . Every labour is to have the intent that the man be satisfied. Therefore he must become a <b>master</b> in it too, be able to perform it as a totality. He who in a pin-factory only puts on heads, only draws the wire, works, as it were mechanically, like a machine; he remains half-trained, does not become a master: his labour cannot <b>satisfy</b> him, it can only <b>fatigue</b> him. His labour is nothing by itself, has no object <b>in itself,</b> is nothing complete in itself; he labours only into another's hands, and is <b>used</b> (exploited) by this other."</i> [<b>The Ego and Its Own</b>,  p. 121] Kropotkin makes a similar argument against the division of labour (<i>"machine-like labour"</i>) in <b>The Conquest of Bread</b> (see chapter  XV -- <i>"The Division of Labour"</i>) as did Proudhon (see chapters III and IV of <b>System of Economical Contradictions</b>).</p>
<p>Modern industry is set up to ensure that workers do not become "masters" of their work but instead follow the orders of management. The evolution of technology lies in the relations of power within a society. This is because <i>"the viability of a design is not simply a technical or even economic evaluation but rather a political one. A technology is deemed viable if it conforms to the existing relations of power."</i> [David Noble, <b>Progress without People</b>, p. 63]</p>
<p>This process of controlling, restricting, and de-individualising labour  is a key feature of capitalism. Work that is skilled and controlled by workers is empowering to them in two ways. Firstly it gives them pride in their work and themselves. Secondly, it makes it harder to replace them or suck profits out of them. Therefore, in order to remove the "subjective" factor (i.e. individuality and worker control) from the  work process, capital needs methods of controlling the workforce to  prevent workers from asserting their individuality, thus preventing  them from arranging their own lives and work and resisting the authority  of the bosses. This need to control workers can be seen from the type of  machinery introduced during the Industrial Revolution. According to  Andrew Ure (author of <b>Philosophy of Manufactures</b>), a consultant for  the factory owners at the time:</p>
<blockquote><p> <i>"In the factories for spinning coarse yarn . . . the mule-spinners  [skilled workers] have abused their powers beyond endurance, domineering  in the most arrogant manner . . . over their masters. High wages, instead of leading to thankfulness of temper and improvement of mind, have, in  too many cases, cherished pride and supplied funds for supporting  refractory spirits in strikes . . . During a disastrous turmoil of [this]  kind . . . several of the capitalists . . . had recourse to the celebrated  machinists . . . of Manchester . . . [to construct] a self-acting mule  . . . This invention confirms the great doctrine already propounded, that  when capital enlists science in her service, the refractory hand of labour  will always be taught docility."</i> [quoted by Noble, <b>Op. Cit.</b>, p. 125]
</p></blockquote>
<p>Proudhon quotes an English Manufacturer who argues the same point:</p>
<blockquote><p> <i>"The insubordination of our workmen has given us the idea of dispensing with them. We have made and stimulated every imaginable effort to replace the service of men by tools more docile, and we have achieved our object. Machinery has delivered capital from the oppression of labour."</i> [<b>System of Economical Contradictions</b>, p. 189]
</p></blockquote>
<p>It is important to stress that technological innovation was not driven by reasons of economic efficiency as such but rather to break the power of workers at the point of production. Once that was done, initially  uneconomic investments could become economically viable. As David Noble  summarises, during the Industrial Revolution <i>"Capital invested in machines  that would reinforce the system of domination [in the workplace], and this  decision to invest, which might in the long run render the chosen technique  economical, was not itself an economical decision but a political one, with  cultural sanction."</i> [<b>Op. Cit.</b>, p. 6]</p>
<p>Needless to say, this use of technology within the class war continued. A similar process was at work in the US, where the rise in trade unionism resulted in <i>"industrial managers bec[oming] even more insistent that skill  and initiative not be left on the shop floor, and that, by the same token,  shop floor workers not have control over the reproduction of relevant  skills through craft-regulated apprenticeship training. Fearful that  skilled shop-floor workers would use their scare resources to reduce  their effort and increase their pay, management deemed that knowledge  of the shop-floor process must reside with the managerial structure."</i>  [William Lazonick, <b>Organisation and Technology in Capitalist  Development</b>, p. 273]</p>
<p>American managers happily embraced Taylorism (aka "scientific management"),  according to which the task of the manager was to gather into his possession  all available knowledge about the work he oversaw and reorganise it. Taylor himself considered the task for workers was <i>"to do what they are told to do promptly and without asking questions or making suggestions."</i> [quoted by David Noble, <b>American By Design</b>, p. 268] Taylor also relied exclusively upon incentive-pay schemes which mechanically linked pay to productivity and had no appreciation of the subtleties of psychology or sociology (which would have told him that enjoyment of work and creativity is more important for people than just higher pay). Unsurprisingly, workers responded to his schemes by insubordination, sabotage and strikes and it was <i>"discovered . . . that the 'time and motion' experts frequently knew very little about the proper work activities under their supervision, that often they simply guessed at the optimum rates for given operations . . . it meant that the arbitrary authority of management has simply been reintroduced in a less apparent form."</i> [David Noble, <b>Op. Cit.</b>, p. 272] Although, now, the power of management could hide begin the "objectivity" of "science."</p>
<p>Katherine Stone also argues that the <i>"transfer of skill [from the  worker to management] was not a response to the necessities of production,  but was, rather, a strategy to rob workers of their power"</i> by <i>"tak[ing] knowledge and authority from the skilled workers and creating a management cadre able to direct production."</i> Stone highlights that this deskilling  process was combined by a <i>"divide and rule"</i> policy by management based  on wage incentives and new promotion policies. This created a reward  system in which workers who played by the rules would receive concrete  gains in terms of income and status. Over time, such a structure would  become to be seen as <i>"the natural way to organise work and one which  offered them personal advancement"</i> even though, <i>"when the system was  set up, it was neither obvious nor rational. The job ladders were created  just when the skill requirements for jobs in the industry were diminishing  as a result of the new technology, and jobs were becoming more and more equal as to the learning time and responsibility involved."</i> The modern  structure of the capitalist workplace was created to break workers  resistance to capitalist authority and was deliberately <i>"aimed at altering  workers' ways of thinking and feeling -- which they did by making workers'  individual 'objective' self-interests congruent with that of the employers  and in conflict with workers' collective self-interest."</i> It was a means of  <i>"labour discipline"</i> and of <i>"motivating workers to work for the employers'  gain and preventing workers from uniting to take back control of  production."</i> Stone notes that the <i>"development of the new labour  system in the steel industry was repeated throughout the economy in different industries. As in the steel industry, the core of these new labour systems were the creation of artificial job hierarchies and the transfer of skills from workers to the managers."</i> [<i>"The Origins of Job  Structure in the Steel Industry,"</i> pp. 123-157, Root &amp; Branch (ed.),  <b>Root and Branch: The Rise of the Workers' Movements</b>, p. 155, p. 153,  p. 152 and pp. 153-4]</p>
<p>This process of deskilling workers was complemented by other factors --  state protected markets (in the form of tariffs and government orders --  the <i>"lead in technological innovation came in armaments where assured  government orders justified high fixed-cost investments"</i>); the use of  <i>"both political and economic power [by American Capitalists] to eradicate  and diffuse workers' attempts to assert shop-floor control"</i>; and <i>"repression,  instigated and financed both privately and publicly, to eliminate radical  elements [and often not-so-radical elements as well, we must note] in the  American labour movement."</i> [William Lazonick, <b>Competitive Advantage on  the Shop Floor</b>, p. 218 and p. 303] Thus state action played a key role  in destroying craft control within industry, along with the large financial  resources of capitalists compared to workers. Bringing this sorry story  up to date, we find <i>"many, if not most, American managers are reluctant  to develop skills [and initiative] on the shop floor for the fear of  losing control of the flow of work."</i> [William Lazonick, <b>Organisation  and Technology in Capitalist Development</b>, pp. 279-280] Nor should we forget that many technologies are the product of state aid. For example, in the case of automation <i>"the state, especially the military, has  played a central role. Not only has it subsidised extravagant developments that the market could not or refused to bear but it absorbed excessive  costs and thereby kept afloat those competitors who would otherwise  have sunk."</i> [<b>Op. Cit.</b>, p. 83]</p>
<p>Given that there is a division of knowledge in society (and, obviously,  in the workplace as well) this means that capitalism has selected to  introduce a management and technology mix which leads to inefficiency  and waste of valuable knowledge, experience and skills. Thus the  capitalist workplace is both produced by and is a weapon in the class  struggle and reflects the shifting power relations between workers and  employers. The creation of artificial job hierarchies, the transfer of  skills away from workers to managers and technological development are  all products of class struggle. Thus technological progress and workplace  organisation within capitalism have little to do with "efficiency" and  far more to do with profits and power. <i>"Capitalism does not utilise a socially nature technology for capitalist ends,"</i> Cornelius Castoriadis  correctly argued. It has <i>"created a capitalist technology, which is by  no means neutral. The real intention of capitalist technology is not  to develop production for production's sake: It is to subordinate  and dominate the producers"</i> and <i>"to eliminate the human element in  productive labour."</i> This means that capitalist technologies will  evolve, that there is <i>"a process of 'natural selection,' affecting technical inventions as they are applied to industry. Some are  preferred to others"</i> and will be <i>"the ones that fit in with capitalism's basic need to deal with labour power as a measurable, supervisable, and interchangeable commodity."</i> Thus technology will be selected <i>"within the framework of its own class rationality."</i> [<b>Social and Political Writings</b>,  vol. 2, p. 104]</p>
<p>This means that while self-management has consistently proven to be more  efficient (and empowering) than hierarchical management structures,  capitalism actively selects <b>against</b> it. This is because capitalism is  motivated purely by increasing the power and profits for the bosses, and  both are best done by disempowering workers and empowering bosses (i.e.  the maximisation of power) -- even though this concentration of power  harms efficiency by distorting and restricting information flow and the  gathering and use of widely distributed knowledge within the firm (as  in any command economy) as well as having a serious impact on the wider  economy and social efficiency. Thus the last refuge of the capitalist or technophile (namely that the productivity gains of technology outweigh  the human costs or the means used to achieve them) is doubly flawed.  Firstly, disempowering technology may maximise profits, but it need not  increase efficient utilisation of resources or workers' time, skills or  potential. Secondly, <i>"when investment does in fact generate innovation,  does such innovation yield greater productivity? . . . After conducting  a poll of industry executives on trends in automation, <b>Business Week</b>  concluded in 1982 that 'there is a heavy backing for capital investment  in a variety of labour-saving technologies that are designed to fatten  profits without necessary adding to productive output.'"</i> David Noble  concludes that <i>"whenever managers are able to use automation to  'fatten profits' and enhance their authority (by eliminating jobs and  extorting concessions and obedience from the workers who remain) without  at the same time increasing social product, they appear more than ready  to do."</i> [David Noble, <b>Progress Without People</b>, pp. 86-87 and p. 89] As we argue in greater detail later, in  <a href="secJ5.html#secj512">section J.5.12</a>, efficiency and  profit maximisation are two different things, with such deskilling and  management control actually <b>reducing</b> efficiency -- compared to workers'  control -- but as it allows managers to maximise profits the capitalist  market selects it.</p>
<p>Of course the claim is that higher wages follow increased investment and technological innovation ("in the long run" -- although usually "the long  run" has to be helped to arrive by workers' struggle and protest!). Passing aside the question of whether slightly increased consumption really makes up for dehumanising and uncreative work, we must note that it is usually the capitalist who <b>really</b> benefits from technological change in money terms. For example, between 1920 and 1927 (a period when unemployment caused by technology became commonplace) the automobile industry (which was at the forefront of technological change) saw wages rise by 23.7%. Thus, claim supporters of capitalism, technology is in all our interests. However, capital surpluses rose by 192.9% during the same period -- 8 times faster! Little wonder wages rose! Similarly, over the last 20 years the USA and many other countries have seen companies "down-sizing" and "right-sizing"  their workforce and introducing new technologies. The result? Simply put, the 1970s saw the start of <i>"no-wage growth expansions."</i> Before the early 1970s, <i>"real wage growth tracked the growth of productivity  and production in the economy overall. After . . ., they ceased to do  so. . . Real wage growth fell sharply below measured productivity growth."</i>  [James K. Galbraith, <b>Created Unequal</b>, p. 79] So while real wages have  stagnated, profits have been increasing as productivity rises and the  rich have been getting richer -- technology yet again showing whose  side it is on.</p>
<p>Overall, as David Noble notes (with regards to manufacturing in the early 1990s):</p>
<blockquote><p> <i>"U.S. Manufacturing industry over the last thirty years . . . [has seen] the value of capital stock (machinery) relative to labour double, reflecting the trend towards mechanisation and automation. As a consequence . . . the absolute output person hour increased 115%, more than double. But during this same period, real earnings for hourly workers . . . rose only 84%, less than double. Thus, after three decades of automation-based progress, workers are now earning less relative to their output than before. That is, they are producing more for less; working more for their boss and less for themselves."</i> [<b>Op. Cit.</b>, pp. 92-3]
</p></blockquote>
<p>Noble continues:</p>
<blockquote><p> <i>"For if the impact of automation on workers has not been ambiguous, neither has the impact on management and those it serves -- labour's loss has been their gain. During the same first thirty years of our age of automation, corporate after tax profits have increased 450%, more than five times the increase in real earnings for workers."</i> [<b>Op. Cit.</b>, p. 95]
</p></blockquote>
<p>But why? Because labour has the ability to produce a flexible amount  of output (use value) for a given wage. Unlike coal or steel, a worker can be made to work more intensely during a given working period and so technology can be utilised to maximise that effort as well as increasing the pool of potential replacements for an employee by deskilling their work (so reducing workers' power to get higher wages for their work). Thus technology is a key way of increasing the power of the boss, which in turn can increase output per worker  while ensuring that the workers'  receive relatively less of that output  back in terms of wages -- <i>"Machines,"</i> argued Proudhon, <i>"promised us an  increase of wealth they have kept their word, but at the same time  endowing us with an increase of poverty. They promised us liberty . . .  [but] have brought us slavery."</i> [<b>Op. Cit.</b>, p. 199]</p>
<p>But do not get us wrong, technological progress does not imply that we are victims. Far from it, much innovation is the direct result of our resistance to hierarchy and its tools. For example, capitalists turned to Taylorism and "scientific management" in response to the  power of skilled craft workers to control their work and working environment (the famous 1892 Homestead strike, for example, was a direct product of the desire of the company to end the skilled  workers' control and power on the shop-floor). Such management  schemes never last in the long run nor totally work in the short  run either -- which explains why hierarchical management continues,  as does technological deskilling. Workers always find ways of using  new technology to increase their power within the workplace,  undermining management decisions to their own advantage). As  left-wing economist William Lazonick puts it:</p>
<blockquote><p> <i>"Because it is the workers, not managers, who are actually doing the work, access to information on the effort-saving potential of a machine will be asymmetric, giving workers a distinct advantage in determining the pace of work. In addition, workers through their unions will attempt to exert industry-wide control over the relation between effort and pay on newly diffused technology. The resultant relation between effort and earnings will depend on the exercise of social power, not on abstract 'laws' of proportional change."</i> [<b>Competitive Advantage on the Shop Floor</b>, pp. 66-7]
</p></blockquote>
<p>This means that the <i>"economic effectiveness of the factory as a mode  of work organisation did not occur within a social vacuum but depend[s] on the historical evolution of conditions that determined the relative  power of capitalists and workers to structure the relation between  effort and pay."</i> As such, it is important not to overemphasise the  <i>"independent influence of technology as opposed to the relations of  production in the determination of work organisation. Because machinery  does change the skill content of work, it can potentially serve as an instrument of social power. How and to what extent it does so, however,  depends not only on the nature of the technology but also on the nature  of the social environment into which it is introduced."</i> Thus the  introduction of machinery into the capitalist labour process <i>"is only  a necessary, not sufficient, condition for the displacement of worker  control over the relation between effort and pay."</i> [Lazonick, <b>Op. Cit.</b>,  p. 52 and p. 63] Needless to say, capitalists have always appealed to the state to help create a suitable social environment.</p>
<p>This analysis applies to both the formal and informal organisation of  workers in workplace. Just as the informal structures and practices  of working people evolve over time in response to new technology and  practices, so does union organisation. In response to Taylorism,  factory and other workers created a whole new structure of working  class power -- a new kind of unionism based on the industrial level.  For example, the IWW was formed specifically to create industrial  unions arguing that <i>"[l]abourers are no longer classified by  difference in trade skill, but the employer assigns them according  to the machine which they are attached. These divisions, far from  representing differences in skill or interests among the labourers,  are imposed by the employers that workers may be pitted against one  another and spurred to greater exertion in the shop, and that all  resistance to capitalist tyranny may be weakened by artificial  distinctions."</i> [quoted by Stone, <b>Op. Cit.</b>, p. 157]</p>
<p>For this reason, anarchists and syndicalists argued for, and built,  industrial unions -- one union per workplace and industry -- in order  to combat these divisions and effectively resist capitalist tyranny.  This can be seen in many different countries. In Spain, the C.N.T. (an  anarcho-syndicalist union) adopted the <b>sindicato unico</b> (one union)  in 1918 which united all workers of the same workplace in the same  union (by uniting skilled and unskilled in a single organisation,  the union increased their fighting power). In the UK, the shop  stewards movement arose during the first world war based on workplace  organisation (a movement inspired by the pre-war syndicalist revolt  and which included many syndicalist activists). This movement was  partly in response to the reformist TUC unions working with the  state during the war to suppress class struggle. In Germany, the 1919 near revolution saw the creation of revolutionary workplace  unions and councils (and a large increase in the size of the  anarcho-syndicalist union FAU which was organised by industry).</p>
<p>This process was not limited to just libertarian unions. In the USA,  the 1930s saw a massive and militant union organising drive by the  C.I.O. based on industrial unionism and collective bargaining (inspired,  in part, by the example of the I.W.W. and its broad organisation of  unskilled workers). More recently, workers in the 1960s and 70s  responded to the increasing reformism and bureaucratic nature of such  unions as the CIO and TUC by organising themselves directly on the  shop floor to control their work and working conditions. This informal  movement expressed itself in wildcat strikes against both unions  and management, sabotage and unofficial workers' control of production  (see John Zerzan's essay <i>"Organised Labour and the Revolt Against Work"</i> in <b>Elements of Refusal</b>). In the UK, the shop stewards'  movement revived itself, organising much of the unofficial strikes  and protests which occurred in the 1960s and 70s. A similar tendency  was seen in many countries during this period.</p>
<p>So in response to a new developments in technology and workplace  organisation, workers' developed new forms of resistance which in turn  provokes a response by management. Thus technology and its (ab)uses are  very much a product of the class struggle, of the struggle for freedom  in the workplace. With a given technology, workers and radicals soon  learn to resist it and, sometimes, use it in ways never dreamed of to  resist their bosses and the state (which necessitates a transformation  of within technology again to try and give the bosses an upper hand!).  The use of the Internet, for example, to organise, spread and co-ordinate  information, resistance and struggles is a classic example of this  process (see Jason Wehling, <i>"'Netwars' and Activists Power on the  Internet"</i>, <b>Scottish Anarchist</b> no. 2 for details). There is  always a "guerrilla war" associated with technology, with workers  and radicals developing their own tactics to gain counter control  for themselves. Thus much technological change reflects <b>our</b>  power and activity to change our own lives and working conditions.  We must never forget that.</p>
<p>While some may dismiss our analysis as "Luddite," to do so is  make "technology" an idol to be worshipped rather than something  to be critically analysed. Indeed, it would be temping to argue  that worshippers of technological progress are, in effect, urging  us <b>not</b> to think and to sacrifice ourselves to a new abstraction  like the state or capital. Moreover, such attacks misrepresent  the ideas of the Luddites themselves -- they never actually opposed  <b>all</b> technology or machinery. Rather, they opposed <i>"all Machinery  hurtful to Commonality"</i> (as a March 1812 letter to a hated Manufacturer  put it). Rather than worship technological progress (or view it  uncritically), the Luddites subjected technology to critical analysis  and evaluation. They opposed those forms of machinery that harmed  themselves or society. Unlike those who smear others as "Luddites,"  the labourers who broke machines were not intimidated by the modern  notion of progress. As John Clark notes, they <i>"chose to smash the  dehumanising machinery being imposed on them, rather than submit  to domination and degradation in the name of technical progress."</i> [<b>The Anarchist Moment</b>, p. 102] Their sense of right and wrong was  not clouded by the notion that technology was somehow inevitable, neutral or to be worshipped without question.</p>
<p>The Luddites did not think that <b>human</b> values (or their own interests)  were irrelevant in evaluating the benefits and drawbacks of a given  technology and its effects on workers and society as a whole. Nor  did they consider their skills and livelihood as less important  than the profits and power of the capitalists. In other words,  they would have agreed with Proudhon's later comment that machinery  <i>"plays the leading role in industry, man is secondary"</i> <b>and</b> they  acted to change this relationship. [<b>Op. Cit.</b>, p. 204] The Luddites  were an example of working people deciding what their interests were  and acting to defend them by their own direct action -- in this case  opposing technology which benefited the ruling class by giving them  an edge in the class struggle. Anarchists follow this critical  approach to technology, recognising that it is not neutral nor  above criticism. That this is simply sensible can be seen from the world around us, where capitalism has, to quote Rocker, made work <i>"soulless and has lost for the individual the quality of creative joy. By becoming a dreary end-in-itself it has degraded man into an eternal galley slave and robbed him of that which is most precious, the inner joy of accomplished work, the creative urge of the personality. The individual feels himself to be only an insignificant element of a gigantic mechanism in whose dull monotone every personal note dies out."</i> He has <i>"became the slave  of the tool he created."</i> There has been a <i>"growth of technology at the expense of human personality."</i> [<b>Nationalism and Culture</b>, p. 253 and p. 254]</p>
<p>For capital, the source of problems in industry is people. Unlike machines, people can think, feel, dream, hope and act. The "evolution" of technology must, therefore, reflect the class struggle within society and the struggle for liberty against the forces of authority. Technology, far from being neutral, reflects the interests of those with power. Technology will only be truly our friend once we control it ourselves and <b>modify</b> to reflect <b>human</b> values (this may mean that some forms of technology will have to be written off and replaces by new forms in a free society).  Until that happens, most technological processes -- regardless of the other advantages they may have -- will be used to exploit and control people. Thus Proudhon's comments that <i>"in the present condition of society, the workshop with its hierarchical organisation, and machinery"</i> could only serve <i>"exclusively the interests of the least numerous, the least industrious, and the wealthiest class"</i> rather than <i>"be employed for the benefit of all."</i> [<b>Op. Cit.</b>, p. 205]</p>
<p>While resisting technological "progress" which is considered harmful to people or the planet (by means up to and including machine breaking) is  essential in the here and now, the issue of technology can only be truly  solved when those who use a given technology control its development,  introduction and use. (<i>"The worker will only respect machinery <b>on the  day</b> when it becomes his friend, shortening his work, rather than as  <b>today</b>, his enemy, taking away jobs, killing workers,"</i> in the words of French syndicalist Emile Pouget [quoted by David Noble, <b>Op. Cit.</b>,  p. 15]).  Little wonder, therefore, that anarchists consider workers'  self-management as a key means of solving the problems created by  technology. Proudhon, for example, argued that the solution to the  problems created by the division of labour and technology could only  be solved by <i>"association"</i>, and <i>"by a broad education, by the obligation  of apprenticeship, and by the co-operation of all who take part in the  collective work."</i>  This would ensure that <i>"the division of labour can  no longer be a cause of degradation for the workman [or workwoman]."</i>  [<b>The General Idea of the Revolution</b>, p. 223]</p>
<p>While as far as technology goes, it may not be enough to get rid of  the boss this is a necessary first step. Unless this is done, it will be impossible to transform existing technologies or create new ones which enhance freedom rather than controlling and shaping the  worker (or user in general) and enhancing the power and profits of  the capitalist. This means that in an anarchist society, technology  would have to be transformed and/or developed which empowered those  who used it, so reducing any oppressive aspects of it. In the words of  Cornelius Castoriadis, the <i>"conscious transformation of technology will  therefore be a central task of a society of free workers."</i> [<b>Op. Cit.</b>, p. 104] As German anarchist Gustav Landauer stressed, most are <i>"completely unaware of how fundamentally the technology of the socialists differs from capitalist technology . . . Technology will, in a cultured people, have to be directed to the psychology of free people who want to use it."</i> This will happen when <i>"the workers themselves determine under what conditions they want to work,"</i> step out of <i>"capitalism mentally and physically"</i>, and <i>"cease playing a role in it and begin to be men [and women]."</i> [<i>"For Socialism,"</i> pp. 184-6, <b>Anarchism</b>, Robert Graham  (ed.), p. 285 and p. 286]</p>
<p>Thus most anarchists would agree with Bookchin's comment that technology <i>"is necessarily liberatory or consistently beneficial to man's  development"</i> but we <i>"do not believe that man is destined to be  enslaved by technology and technological modes of thought."</i> A free society <i>"will not want to negate technology precisely because it is liberated and can strike a balance"</i> and create a <i>"technology for life,"</i> a liberatory technology based on human and ecological needs. [<b>Op. Cit.</b>,  p. 43 and p. 80] See <a href="secI4.html#seci49">section I.4.9</a>  for more discussion on technology within an anarchist society.</p>
  <div id="book-navigation-239" class="book-navigation">

        <div class="page-links clear-block">
              <a href="secD9.html" class="page-previous" title="Go to previous page">‹ D.9 Why does political power become concentrated under capitalism?</a>
                    <a href="secDcon.html" class="page-up" title="Go to parent page">up</a>
                    <a href="secD11.html" class="page-next" title="Go to next page">D.11 Can politics and economics be separated from each other? ›</a>
          </div>

  </div>
  </div>
  </body>
</html>